Birthright Questions, Founding Answers
The Declaration and the Fourteenth Amendment grasped citizenship through social compact.
americanmind.org
Based where the founders came from and how the country was founded on the consent of the governed. I don't believe you can have birthright citizenship in a country that is for the people by the people.
Most of what I am going to post is quotes from the link. This guy says it better than I can.
Birthright citizenship:
Currently thought of American practice adopted the English common law of jus solis. The authoritative source for the English common law at the time of the founding was William Blackstone. Well known to the Founders themselves, Blackstone always speaks of “natural born subjects” who owe the obligation of “perpetual allegiance” for having been born within the protection of the King. Blackstone admits this was an inheritance from the “feudal system,” deriving from the “mutual trust or confidence subsisting between the lord and vassal.” Blackstone never uses the word “citizen” or “citizenship,” because under the common law there are no citizens, only subjects who owe “perpetual allegiance” that they do not freely choose.
Why this can't be:
Under the common law the colonists owed “perpetual allegiance.” Here they are absolving themselves of that allegiance and dissolving relations with Great Britain without the King’s permission in clear violation of the common law. The common law of jus solis, entailing perpetual allegiance—that relic of feudalism—is not compatible with the principles of the Declaration of Independence, those principles intended to translate subjects into citizens who possess rights and freely accept obligations.
One could hardly argue that subjects and citizens are convertible terms—yet the Supreme Court actually did so in the case of U.S. v. Wong Kim Ark (1898), ruling that the Fourteenth Amendment adopted the common law basis for citizenship. It is clear, however, from the obvious meaning of the Declaration that by absolving “Allegiance” to the Crown the American people rejected British common law and replaced subjectship with citizenship.
The Basis for Citizenship in the American Founding:
The American Revolution decisively rejected the concept of “natural born subjects”—a feudal relic of the British common law—and instituted a basis for citizenship that was grounded in republicanism derived from the principles of the American Revolution.
The principles of the American Revolution replaced the prescriptive or historical rights of the English common law with natural rights. Blackstone had spoken of “natural born subjects”—a phrase not out of place in feudalism—but the notion of “natural born subjects” utterly contradicts the Declaration and its central principle that “all men are created equal.” If Jus solis were the basis for citizenship, citizenship would be based solely on the accident of birth. Thomas Jefferson, in the Summary View of the Rights of British America (1774) argued that all human beings possessed a natural right to expatriation, “of departing from the country in which chance, not choice has placed them.” Choice, of course, implies reason—and reason is the foundation of natural right. Expatriation was prohibited by the common law, on the other hand, because it would violate the obligation of “perpetual allegiance.”
Expatriation is not the only natural right that is not allowed to “natural born subjects” owing “perpetual allegiance” under the English common law. Natural born subjects do not possess the right that protects every other right—the right to “alter or abolish government” when it fails to secure the “safety and happiness” of the people—or, in other words, to absolve allegiance and dissolve political connections.
The Declaration specifies that the “just powers” of government derive from “the consent of the governed.” Choice implies deliberation, and deliberation and choice are the essential ingredients in the establishment of government. One might even say that that “accident and force” is the leitmotif of the common law.
The same choice is essential to citizenship. James Madison is not only famous for his insistence that the Constitution derives its authoritative principles from the Declaration, but also for his oft-repeated statement that “all power in just & free Govt is derived from compact.” Madison undoubtedly regarded the Declaration as the quintessential example of social compact where citizenship was based on the consent of each individual who chose to enter civil society for the equal protection of equal rights.
Thus social compact, not jus solis, was the new basis for citizenship.
The Founding generation was virtually unanimous that social compact was the rightful and just basis for civil society and that consent was the basis for citizenship. A good example of that consensus is the Massachusetts Bill of Rights (1780) written by John Adams, coauthor of the Declaration. The preface to that notable document is as perfect an expression of social compact as can be found:
The end of the institution, maintenance, and administration of government, is to secure the existence of the body politic, to protect it, and to furnish the individuals, who compose it, with the power of enjoying, in safety and tranquility, their natural rights, and the blessings of life: and whenever these great objects are not obtained, the people have a right to alter the government, and to take measures, necessary for their safety, prosperity, and happiness. The body politic is formed by a voluntary association of individuals. It is a social compact, by which the whole people covenants with each citizen, and each citizen with the whole people, that all shall be governed by certain laws for the common good. It is the duty of the people, therefore, in framing a Constitution of Government, to provide for an equitable mode of making laws, as well as for an impartial interpretation, and a faithful execution of them; that every man may, at all times, find his security in them.
14th Amendment:
The Fourteenth Amendment’s qualification for birthright citizenship—those “subject to the jurisdiction”—does not mean subject to the law or to the courts. That is the definition of “jurisdiction” in the law dictionary, but it is not what the framers of the Citizenship Clause said it meant. An original intent jurisprude must credit the framers of the amendment above the authors of legal dictionaries.
But the most fundamental reason we should understand the Amendment this way is not simply because the framers said so, but why.
The principal framers of the Fourteenth Amendment said that “subject to the jurisdiction” meant “subject to the complete jurisdiction” of the United States, “owing allegiance to no other country.” I provided ample evidence in my earlier remarks to prove this point. There is no evidence whatsoever from the congressional debates that “subject to the jurisdiction” mean simply “subject to the laws and the courts.” As I demonstrated with multiple references to the legislative history, the language of “allegiance” was not merely contained in “scattered” references as Judge Ho claims.
Why the framers didn’t use the phrase “subject to the allegiance” in the amendment instead of “subject to the jurisdiction”, if that is what they meant. But, as I indicated previously, Senator Trumbull, author of the Civil Rights Act of 1866, said he considered the language of “allegiance” as a qualification of citizenship, but rejected it because it was a term of art under the common law—and would have required granting citizenship to those temporarily in the country who owed no allegiance to the United States!
The Civil Rights Act was passed over President Andrew Johnson’s veto less than two months prior to debate over the Citizenship Clause in the Senate. Most of the Senators who debated the Clause were part of the two-thirds majority who voted for the Act and presumably agreed with Senator Howard when he said that the Clause reflected the law as it already existed. As Professor Yoo recounts, the Civil Rights Act denied birthright citizenship, not only to “Indians not taxed,” but those “subject to any foreign power.”
If birthright citizenship was denied to those “subject to any foreign power”, how can it be argued that everyone born within US territory is automatically a natural born citizen of the United States?
Thank you to the guy in the link that wrote this. This is my third or fourth time arguing this and I always point to this guy's works.